Page:Encyclopædia Britannica, Ninth Edition, v. 10.djvu/117

From Wikisource
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This page needs to be proofread.
GAS—GAT
107

It is divided, according to the usual fashion of the Epicure- ans, into logic (which, with Gassendi as with Epicurus, is truly anionic), physics, and ethics. The logic, which con- tains at least one praiseworthy portion, a sketch of the history of the science, is divided into theory of right appre- hension (beue imaginari), theory of right judgment (bene proponere), theory of right inference (bene coll-igerc), theory of right method (bane ordinare). The first part contains the specially empirical positions which Gassendi afterwards neglects 01' leaves out of account. The senses, the sole source of knowledge, are supposed to yield us immediately cognition of individual things; phantasy (which Gasscndi takes to be material in nature) reproduces these ideas; understanding compares these ideas, which are particular, and frames general ideas. Nevertheless, he at the same time admits that the senses yield knowledge—not of things—but of qualities only, and holds that we arrive at the idea of thing or substance by induction. He holds that the true method of research is the analytic, rising from lower to higher notions , yet he sees clearly, and admits, that inductive reasoning, as conceived by Bacon, rests on a general proposition not itself proved by induction. He ought to hold, and in disputing with Descartes he did apparently hold, that the evidence of the senses is the only convincing evidence; yet he maintains, and from his special mathematical training it was natural he should maintain, that the evidence of reason is absolutely satis- factory. The whole doctrine of judgment, syllogism, and

method is a mixture of Aristotelian and Ramist notions.

In the second part of the Syntayma, the physics, there is more that deserves attention ; but here, too, appears in the most glaring manner the inner contradiction between Gassendi’s fundamental principles. While approving of the Epicurean physics, he rejects altogether the Epicurean negation of God and particular providence. He states the various proofs for the existence of an immaterial, infinite, supreme Being, asserts that this Being is the author of the visible universe, and strongly defends the doctrine of the foreknowledge and particular providence of God. At the same time he holds, in opposition to Epicureanism, the doctrine of an immaterial, rational soul, endowed with im- mortality and capable of free determination. It is alto- gether impossible to assent to the supposition of Lange (Gesc/z. des Jflrterialismus, 3d ed., i. 233), that all this portion of Gassendi’s system contains nothing of his own opinions, but is solely introduced from motives of self- defence. The positive exposition of atomism has much that is attractive, but the hypothesis of the calor citalis, a species of anima mmzdi which is introduced as physical explanation of physical phenomena, does not seem to throw much light on the special problems which it is invoked to solve. Nor is his theory of the weight essential to atoms as being due to an inner force impelling them to motion in any way reconcilable with his general doctrine of me- chanical causes.

In the third part, the ethics, over and above the discussion on freedom, which on the whole is indefinite, there is little beyond a milder statement of the Epicurean moral code. The final end of life is happiness, and happiness is harmony of soul and body, tranquillitas animi et indolentia comoris. Probably, Gassendi thinks, perfect happiness is not attain- able in this life, but it may be in the life to come.

The Syntagmais thus an essentially unsystematic work, and clearly exhibits the main characteristics of Gassendi’s genius. He was critical rather than constructive, widely read and trained thoroughly both in languages and in seience, but deficient in speculative power and original force. Even in the department of natural science he shows the same inability steadfastly to retain principles and to work from them ; he wavers between the systems of Brahe and Copernicus. That his revival of Epicureanism had an im- portant influence on the general thinking of the 17th century may be admitted ; that it has any real importance in the history of philosophy cannot be granted.


Gassendi’s life is given by Sorbiere in the first collected edition of the works, by Bugercl, l'z'c dc Gassendi, 1737 (2d ed., 1770), and by Damiron, Jilc’moirc sur Gassendi, 1839. An abridgment of his philosophy was given by his friend, the celebrated traveller, Bernicr (Abrégé dc la I’lu'losophz’c do Gassendi, 8 vols. , 1678 ; 2d ed., 7 vols. , 1684). The most complete surVeys of his work seem to be those of Buhlc (Gcschz'chtc dcr mucrn Philosophic, iii. , 1, 87—222), and Damiron (Jlémoz'rcs pour scrm'r a l’IIistoz'rc dc I’hilosophic cm 17""? Siéclc.) See also Bitter, Gcschichtc dcr Philosophic, x- 543-571; Feucrbach, Gcsch. d. mu. I’Iu'l. um Bacon bis Spinoza, 127450.

(r. ad.)

GASTEIN, a beautiful and picturesque valley in the Austrian duchy of Salzburg, celebrated for its mineral springs. It is a side valley of the upper Salzach valley, and is about 25 miles long and 1;}- miles broad. It has an elevation of between 3000 and 3500 feet. Behind it, to the south, tower the mountains Malnitz or Nassfeld-Tauern, 7820 feet high, and the Ankogel, 10,700 feet high, and from the right and left of these mountains two smaller ranges run northwards forming its two side walls. The river Ache traverses the valley, and near Wildbad-Gastein forms two magnificent waterfalls, the upper, the Kesselfall, 200 feet, and the lower, the Barenfall, 280 feet in height; and near these falls another called the Schleierfall, 250 feet high, is formed by the stream which drains the Pockhart-See. The principal villages are B'ockstein, Hof—Gast-ein, and Wildbad- Gastein, and the population of the whole valley is about 3800. Hof—Gastein, with a population of about 1000. possesses gold and silver mines which in the 16th century yielded 1180 lb of gold and 9500 lb of silver annually. They are now, however, much neglected and many of the old mines are covered by glaciers. The village contains a military hospital, and in the open platz there is a bust of the emperor Francis I. who, in 1828, caused a conduit of upwards of 5 miles long to be constructed for the purpose of conveying the mineral waters thither from Wildbad. IVildbad, the principal watering-place, is visited by upwards of 3000 persons annually, and among its visitors is the pre- sent emperor of Germany. The thermal springs, which were known as early as the 7th century, issue from the granite mountains, and have a temperature of 117° Fahr. They are made use of in cases of nervous affections, general debility, and skin diseases ; but the reason of their efficacy is somewhat mysterious, as chemical analysis discovers only a slight difference in the ingredients from those of ordinary spring water. The village is formed chiefly of wooden houses rising above one another in terraces. A number of stone houses have, however, been built of late; and there are several fine villas, one of which was constructed by the archduke John of Austria, and has a botanical garden.


The baths of Gastein first came into fame through a successful visit paid to them by Duke Frederick of Austria in 1436. The valley from the 11th century belonged to the dukes of Peilstein, and on the extinction of their line in 1219 it came into possession of Bavaria, whence it passed in 1297 by purchase to Salzburg. A convention was held at Wildbad-Gastein in August 1865, between the emperor Francis Joseph of Austria and King William of Prussia, at which an arrangement was signed in reference to the relations of Austria and Prussia to Sehleswig-Holstein and Lauenburg (see Austria).

The principal books on Gastein are Reissacher, Der Kin-art TVzl_d-bad-Gastein, 1865 ; Bunzel, Bad—Gastcin, 1872; Henigsberg, Gastcm, 1873; and A Month at Gastez’u, London, n.d. .

GATAKER, Thomas (1574–1654), a learned English

divine, was born in London in 1574, and educated at St John’s College, Cambridge. From 1601 to 1611 he held the appointment of preacher to the society of Lincoln’s Inn, which he resigned on obtaining the rectory

of Rotherhithe. In 1642 he was chosen a member of the